Feeds:
Posts
Comments

Archive for September, 2009

HUHI 6305 students – this is a description of a research project that I’ve been working on lately that I’ve been planning on discussing a bit on the blog, not because it is relevant to any particular week’s discussion, but because it is an interesting case study for supplementing the general discussions of the course, exemplifying many of the themes that carry on from week to week. I also want to put it up as an example of what I’m looking for in your project descriptions for those choosing the blog-based option

Everyone: I would be grateful for any comments or references on the abstract and the themes I’m planning to discuss. I’ve been engaged in work on Marston and close reading of his theories for some time, but this is my first major research project in history and philosophy of psychology, and I would appreciate pointers.

Abstract

While at best, William Moulton Marston is remembered today in the history of psychology for making contributions to the creation of the lie detector test, he was in his time, particularly in the 1920’s, a major figure both within the discipline of psychology and in the public eye. Indeed, at his peak Marston’s public exposure probably rivaled the likes of Freud, Skinner, or Chomsky as a public face of psychology, though his theories had nothing like their lasting influence, and his time in the limelight was considerably shorter. Despite the fact that his theories had little impact on the subsequent development of the field of psychology, Marston’s work is instructive in several ways for philosophers of science and philosophers of psychology. Besides being a highly interesting early attempt to draw conclusions about emotions and cognition on the basis of work in neuroscience, it is an interesting case study in the relation between science and values. Marston’s research is inflected by his (unorthodox) feminist values and parallels in important ways the work of feminist scientists since the 1980’s who have insisted that the introduction of enlightened (including feminist) values into scientific research can be a positive methodological resource. Marston’s theories also imply strong normative conclusions for psycho-emotional health and education, claims which do not depend on and are not consistent with statistically average behavior or dominant social norms. His book on the emotions culminates in a chapter on emotional re-education, which he later enacts through various forms of what he calls “psychological propaganda”: popular psychology books like Try Living (1937) and March On! (1941), articles on psychology for various magazines like Cosmopolitan, Good Housekeeping, and Reader’s Digest, a novel called Venus With Us: A Tale of the Caesar (1932) and creating the iconic comic book superheroine, Wonder Woman (the other achievement for which Marston is very well known). Marston thus provides us with an unusual study of the goals and applications of psychological research, including the potential uses of popularization and popular culture as a mode of scientific application. In this essay, I will examine the main features of Marston’s psychological theories, primarily as set out in his main works, The Emotions of Normal People (1928) and Integrative Psychology (1931), against the context of Marston’s values as exhibited through his statements and what is known about his personal life. I will look at the mutual interactions between science and values in his work: first, I will examine the parallels between Marston’s work and other value-laden feminist research; then, I will look at the various ways that Marston applies his research towards the attempt to reform individuals and society.

Read Full Post »

This week, we’re discussing the first four chapters of George Reisch’s book, How the Cold War Transformed Philosophy of Science, Don Howard’s “Two Left Turns Make a Right” (from Logical Empiricism in North America, which also has several other great essays), and Alan Richardson’s “Engineering Philosophy of Science: American Pragmatism and Logical Empiricism in the 1930s”

In the Introduction to Science, Truth, and Democracy, Philip Kitcher begins,

From time to time, when I explain to a new acquaintance that I’m a philosopher of science, my interlocutor will nod agreeably and remark that that surely means I’m interested in the ethical status of various kinds of scientific research, the impact that science has had on our values, or the role that the sciences play in contemporary democracies. Although this common response hardly corresponds to what professional philosophers of science have done for the past decades, or even centuries, it is perfectly comprehensible. (xi, emphasis added)

And later, he describes his book “as an attempt to venture into areas that philosophers of science have neglected“(xiii, likewise).

One of the goals of this week’s readings is to call into question the historical claim that the sort of topics discussed by Kitcher (and likewise, by Longino, Kourany, etc.) have been generally neglected by philosophers of science.

(more…)

Read Full Post »

I didn’t manage a follow-up to my post on the first part of Kitcher’s book. This is actually a topic I’ve written about, so you can see my thoughts on Kitcher in the early sections of that paper. I seem to have failed to convince anybody in class that “curiosity” is not a good way of capturing the whole of epistemic significance, but it is one of my main arguments in the paper. (I’m working on getting that paper published, so any comments on it would be appreciated.)

I’d like to talk a little bit about Kitcher’s recommendation for understanding the role of science in a democracy. First, let me point out what I think is an inconsistency in Kitcher’s setup for the discussion.

(more…)

Read Full Post »

Philip Kitcher’s Science, Truth, and Democracy aims to give much-needed attention to those questions which, in his estimation, philosophy of science ought to be able to answer: “the ethical status of various kinds of scientific research, the impact that science has had on our values, [and] the role that the sciences play in contemporary democracies”(xi).  These questions are, Kitcher thinks, both natural ones deserving to be posed and answered, as well as ones that are traditionally ignored by philosophers of science.

In the book, Kitcher is contending with two extreme perspectives on science, the “science enthusiasts” who believe that true science is the pure search for objective knowledge, to which questions of ethics, values, and politics are irrelevant, and the “science detractors” who deny that objectivity, viewing science as thoroughly infected by values and politics, in such a way that science tends to be an “instrument of oppression”(xi).

Kitcher’s via media is to provide a two-part account of the proper role of science in a democracy. In the first part, Kitcher argues against the detractors that science is, indeed, an objective, truth-seeking enterprise, but against the enthusiasts, he argues that the contents of science are contextual and interest-relative—both what we inquire into and the categories that structure are inquiry are sensitive to our interests and purposes. This part culminates in the claim that what science seeks is not mere truth, but significant truth, and scientific significance is a matter of the practical and epistemic interests served by various scientific ideas and projects, along with the myriad logical and empirical connections between them. Today’s reading covers this first part.

In the second part, this contextual representation of scientific significance is used as an input to an ideal democratic procedure—a deliberation between idealized representatives of the preferences of actual citizens take up this information, mutually inform one another about their preferences, with the goal of consensus at best, or a majority-supported compromise at worst—with the output being the ideal research agenda for science, a schedule of priorities for research meeting the interests and purposes of our society. Kitcher calls this ideal “well-ordered science,” and setting out this ideal, defending it, and tracing its consequences for the responsibilities of actually practicing scientists is the main goal of the second half of the book, which we will discuss next week.

To start off the discussion, let me just raise some questions about Part 1:

(more…)

Read Full Post »

Time to finish up my thoughts on the first section of The Challenge of the Social and the Pressure of Practice. If you haven’t done so, you might want to read my earlier post first. I hope you’ll share your thoughts as well.

One thing we don’t want to do in this complex and controversial discussion of science and values is to talk past one another, to seem to agree or disagree when we are in fact talking about different subjects. One way we might make that mistake is to not specify, or not be clear about, where, exactly, science is supposed to be influenced by values. The authors in this section are, by and large, fairly clear about this, though you might miss it if you don’t look to carefully.

(more…)

Read Full Post »